Rosa Luxemburg and the party
Platypus Review #86 | May 2016
IN ONE OF HER EARLIEST INTERVENTIONS in the Social-Democratic Party of Germany (SPD), participating in the notorious theoretical âRevisionist Dispute,â in which Eduard Bernstein infamously stated that âthe movement is everything, the goal nothing,â the 27 year-old Rosa Luxemburg (1871â1919) clearly enunciated her Marxism: âIt is the final goal alone which constitutes the spirit and the content of our socialist struggle, which turns it into a class struggle.â (( Selected Political Writings of Rosa Luxemburg, ed. Dick Howard (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971), 38â39; also available on-line at: <https://www.marxists.org/archive/luxemburg/1898/10/04.htm>. ))
Critique of socialism
What did it mean to say that socialist politics was necessary to have âclass struggleâ at all? This goes to the heart of Luxemburgâs own Marxism, and to her most enduring contribution to its history: her Marxist approach to the political party for socialismâa dialectical understanding of class and party, in which Marxism itself was grasped in a critical-dialectical way. When Luxemburg accused Bernstein of being âundialectical,â this is what she meant: That the working classâs struggle for socialism was itself self-contradictory and its political party was the means through which this contradiction was expressed. There was a dialectic of means and ends, or of âmovementâ and âgoal,â in which the dialectic of theory and practice took part: Marxism demanded its own critique. Luxemburg took the controversy of the Revisionist Dispute as an occasion for this critique.
In this, Luxemburg followed the young Karl Marxâs (1818â83) own formative dialectical critiques of socialism when he was in his 20s, from the September 1843 letter to Arnold Ruge calling for the âruthless critique of everything existing,â to the critique of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon in the 1844 Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts and The Poverty of Philosophy (1847), as well as in The German Ideology and its famous Theses on Feuerbach (1845). Marx had written of the socialist movement that:
The internal difficulties seem to be almost greater than the external obstacles . . .
[W]e must try to help the dogmatists to clarify their propositions for themselves. Thus, communism, in particular, is a dogmatic abstraction; in which connection, however, I am not thinking of some imaginary and possible communism, but actually existing communism as taught by Cabet, DĂ©zamy, Weitling, etc. This communism is itself only a special expression of the humanistic principle, an expression which is still infected by its antithesisâthe private system. Hence the abolition of private property and communism are by no means identical, and it is not accidental but inevitable that communism has seen other socialist doctrinesâsuch as those of Fourier, Proudhon, etc.âarising to confront it because it is itself only a special, one-sided realisation of the socialist principle . . .
Hence, nothing prevents us from making criticism of politics, participation in politics, and therefore real struggles, the starting point of our criticism, and from identifying our criticism with them. . . . We do not say to the world: Cease your struggles, they are foolish; we will give you the true slogan of struggle. We merely show the world what it is really fighting for . . .
The reform of consciousness consists only in making the world aware of its own consciousness, in awakening it out of its dream about itself, in explaining to it the meaning of its own actions.
Such formulations recurred in Marxâs Theses on Feuerbach a couple of years later:
But that the secular basis detaches itself from itself and establishes itself as an independent realm in the clouds can only be explained by the cleavages and self-contradictions within this secular basis. The latter must, therefore, in itself be both understood in its contradiction and revolutionized in practice.
For Marx, this meant that socialism was the expression of the contradiction of capitalism and as such was itself bound up in that contradiction. A proper dialectical relation of socialism with capitalism required a recognition of the dialectic within socialism itself. Marx followed Hegel in regarding contradiction as manifestation of the need for change. The âproletariatââthe working class after the Industrial Revolutionâcontradicted bourgeois society, not from outside but from within. As such, the contradiction of capitalism centered on the proletariat itself. This is because for Marx âcapitalismâ is nothing in itself, but only the crisis of bourgeois society in industrial production and hence its only meaning is the expression of the need for socialism. The very existence of the proletariatâa working class expropriated from its bourgeois property-rights in labor as a commodityâdemanded socialism.
Lassallean party
But had the social-democratic workersâ party been from its outset a force for counterrevolutionâfor preserving capitalismârather than for revolutionary transformation and the achievement of socialism? Its roots in Ferdinand Lassalleâs formulation of its purpose as the âpermanent political campaign of the working classâ evinced a potential contradiction between its Lassalleanism and Marxism. Marxists had not invented the social-democratic workersâ party, but rather joined it as an emergent phenomenon of the late 19th century. The social-democratic workersâ party in Germany, what became the SPD, had, through its fusion of 1875 at Gotha, attained Marxist or ârevolutionaryâ leadership. But this had elicited Marxâs famous Critique of the Gotha Programme, to which Marxâs own followers, Wilhelm Liebknecht and August Bebel, could only shrug their shoulders at the difficulty of pleasing the âold men in Londonâ (that is, Marx and Engels). The development of the SPD towards its conscious direction beyond mere Lassalleanism was more clearly enunciated in the SPDâs Erfurt Programme of 1891. Nonetheless the ghost of Lassalle seemed to haunt subsequent developments and was still present, according to Engelsâs critique of it, in the âMarxistâ Erfurt Programme itself. (Indeed, one of Rosa Luxemburgâs earliest achievements in her participation in the life of the SPD was to unearth and discover the significance of Engelsâs critique of Bebel, Kautsky, and Bernsteinâs Erfurt Programme.)
Luxemburg, in her critique of the SPD through regarding the party as a manifestation of contradiction, followed Marx and Engels, whose recognition was the means to advance it beyond itself. Lassalle had made the mistake of opposing the political against and derogating the economic action of the workers, rejecting labor unions, which he called merely the âvain efforts of things to behave like human beings.â (( Quoted in Georg LukĂĄcs,âThe Standpoint of the Proletariat,â Part III of âReification and the Consciousness of the Proletariatâ in History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics (1923), trans. Rodney Livingstone (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1971), 195. Available online at: <https://www.marxists.org/archive/lukacs/works/history/hcc07_5.htm>. )) Lassalle thus ontologized the political struggle. For Lassalle, the workers taking political power would be tantamount to the achievement of socialism; whereas for Marx this would be merely a transitional revolutionary âdictatorship of the proletariatâ that would lead to socialism. Engels called it the transition from the âgoverning of menâ to the âadministration of thingsââan eminently dialectical formulation, since humans are both subjects and objects of society.
Lassalleâs political ontology of socialism was complementary to the one-sided âvulgar Marxistâ misapprehensions of the Revisionists who prioritized and indeed ontologized the economic over the political, reducing the social to the economic, and relating the social to the political âmechanicallyâ and âundialecticallyââneglecting the contradiction between them in an âeconomic determinismâ that subordinated politics. Where Lassalle subordinated economics to politics in a âstate socialism,â Marx regarded this rather as a state capitalism. Indeed, despite or rather due to this antinomy, the Lassalleans and the economistic reformists actually converged in their political perspectivesâgiving rise later to 20th century welfare-state capitalism through the governance of social-democratic parties.
Rather than taking one side over the other, Luxemburg, as a Marxist, approached this problem as a real contradiction: an antinomy and dialectic of capitalism itself that manifested in the workersâ own discontents and struggles within it, both economically and politically. For instance, Luxemburg followed Marx in recognizing that the Lassallean goal of the workers achieving a âfree stateâ in political revolution was a self-contradiction: An unfree society gave rise to an unfree state; and it was society that needed to be emancipated from capitalism. But this was a contradiction that could be posed only by the workersâ revolutionary political action and seizing of state powerâif only to âwitherâ it away in the transformation of society beyond capitalism. In this way the Lassallean party was not a mistake but rather a necessary stage manifesting in the history of the workersâ movement. So it needed to be properly recognizedââdialecticallyââin order to avoid its one-sided pitfalls in the opposition of Revisionist, reformist economic evolutionism versus the Lassallean political revolutionism. Kautsky followed Marx in a critical endorsement of Lassalleanism in regarding the dictatorship of the proletariat as the seizing of state power by the workersâ party for socialism. Hence, Luxemburg expressed her sincere âgratitudeâ that the Revisionists had occasioned this critical self-recognition, by posing the question and problem of âmovementâ and âgoal.â
Antinomy of reformism
Luxemburg made her great entrance onto the political stage of her time with the pamphlet Social Reform or Revolution? (1900). In it, Luxemburg laid out how the original contradiction of capitalism, between its chaotic social relations and its socialization of production had been further developed, exacerbated, and deepened by the development of a new contradiction, namely the growth of the workersâ movement in political organization and consciousness: Its movement for socialism was a self-contradictory expression of the contradiction of capitalism. This contrasted with Bernsteinâs view that the growth and development of the workers' movement was the overcoming of the contradiction of capitalism and the gradual âevolutionâ of socialism. For Bernstein, the movement for socialism was the achievement of socialism, whereas the goal of socialism was a dispensable figment, a useful enabling fiction.
For Luxemburg, however, the contradiction of the industrial forces of production against their bourgeois social relations in capitalism was recapitulated in the contradiction between the means and ends of the workersâ movement for socialism. Socialism was not built up within capitalism; but only the contradiction of capital deepened through workersâ struggle against exploitation. How so? Their demand for a share of the value of production was a bourgeois demand: the demand for the value of their labor as a commodity. However, what was achieved by increases in wages, recognition of collective bargaining rights, legal protections of workers in capitalist labor contracts and the acceptance of responsibility of the state for the conditions of labor, including the acceptance of the right to political association and democratic political participation in the state, was not the overcoming of the problem of capitalâthat is, the overcoming of the great divergence and social contradiction between the value of capital and wages in industrial productionâbut rather its exacerbation and deepening through its broadening onto society as a whole. What the workers received in reforms of capitalism was not the value of their labor-power as a commodity, which was relatively minimized by developments of industrial technique, but rather a cut of the profits of capital, whether directly through collective bargaining with the employers or indirectly through state distribution of social welfare benefits from the tax on capital. What Bernstein described optimistically as the socialization of production through such reforms was actually, according to Luxemburg, the âsocializationâ of the crisis of capitalist production.
The workersâ party for socialism, through its growth and development on a mass scale, thus increasingly took political responsibility for capitalism. Hence, a new contradiction developed that was focused on the party itself. Was its purpose to manage capitalism, or rather, as Luxemburg put it in her 1898 Stuttgart speech, to âplay the role of the banker-lawyer who liquidates a bankrupt companyâ? Luxemburg posed the political task of the socialist party in Reform or Revolution? succinctly: âIt is an illusion, then, to think that the proletariat can create economic power within capitalist society. It can only create political power and then transform [aufheben] capitalist property.â The proletarian socialist party was the means for creating that political power. This differed from the development of bourgeois social relations in feudalism that led to revolution:
What does it mean that the earlier classes, particularly the third estate, conquered economic power before political power? Nothing more than the historical fact that all previous class struggles must be derived from the economic fact that the rising class has at the same time created a new form of property upon which it will base its class domination.
However, according to Luxemburg, âThe assertion that the proletariat, in contrast to all previous class struggles, pursues its battles, not in order to establish class domination, but to abolish all class domination is not a mere phrase.â This is because the proletariat does not develop a new form of âpropertyâ within capitalism, but rather struggles economically, socially and politically, on the basis of âbourgeois propertyââon the basis of the bourgeois social relations of labor, or of labor as a commodity. What the working classâs struggle within capitalism achieves is consciousness of the need to overcome labor as a commodity, or, to transform capital from bourgeois property into social property that is no longer mediated by the exchange of labor. This is what it meant for Marx that the proletariat struggles not to ârealizeâ but to abolish itself, or, how the proletariat goes from being a class âin itselfâ to becoming a class âfor itselfâ (The Poverty of Philosophy, 1847) in its struggle for socialism.
For Luxemburg, the achievement of reforms within capitalism accomplish nothing but the greater practical and theoretical realization, or âconsciousness,â of the need to abolish labor as a commodity, since the latter has been outstripped by industrial production. The further economic, social, and political reforms only dramatically increase this disparity and contradiction between the economic value of labor as a commodity and the social value of capital that must be appropriated by society as a whole.
In other words, the workersâ movement for socialism and its institution as a political party is necessary to make the otherwise chaotic, unconscious, âobjectiveâ phenomenon of the economic contradiction and crisis of wage-labor and capital into a conscious, âsubjectiveâ phenomenon of politics. As Luxemburg wrote later, in The Crisis of German Social Democracy (AKA the âJunius Pamphlet,â 1915):
Socialism is the first popular movement in world history that has set itself the goal of bringing human consciousness, and thereby free will, into play in the social actions of mankind. For this reason, Friedrich Engels designated the final victory of the socialist proletariat a leap of humanity from the animal world into the realm of freedom. This âleapâ is also an iron law of history bound to the thousands of seeds of a prior torment-filled and all-too-slow development. But this can never be realized until the development of complex material conditions strikes the incendiary spark of conscious will in the great masses. The victory of socialism will not descend from heaven. It can only be won by a long chain of violent tests of strength between the old and the new powers. The international proletariat under the leadership of the Social Democrats will thereby learn to try to take its history into its own hands; instead of remaining a will-less football, it will take the tiller of social life and become the pilot to the goal of its own history.
Why âviolent tests of strengthâ? Was this mere ârevolutionaryâ passion, as Bernstein averred? No: As Marx had observed in Das Kapital, in the struggle over the âworking day,â or over the social and legal conventions for the condition of labor-time, workers and capitalists confronted each other, both with âbourgeois rightâ on their side. But, âWhere right meets right, force will decide.â Such contests of force did not decide the issue of right in capitalism, but only channeled it in a political direction. Both capital and wage-labor retained their social rights, but the political arena in which their claims were decided shifted from civil society to the state, posing a crisisâthe need for ârevolution.â
1848: state and revolution
For Luxemburg, the modern state was itself merely the âproduct of the last revolution,â namely the political institutionalization of the condition of class struggle up to that point. The âlast revolutionâ was that of 1848, in which the âsocial questionâ was posed as a crisis of the democratic republic. As such, the state remained both the subject and the object of revolutionary politics. Marx had conflicted with the anarchists in the First International over the issue of the need for âpoliticalâ as well as âsocial actionâ in the working classâs struggle for socialism. The Revisionists such as Bernstein had, to Luxemburgâs mind, reverted to the pre-Marxian socialism of anarchism in abandoning the struggle for political power in favor of merely social action. In this, Luxemburg characterized Bernstein as having regressed (like the anarchists) to mere âliberalism.â What Bernstein like the anarchists denied was what Marx had discovered in the experience of the revolutions of 1848, namely, the necessity of the âdictatorship of the proletariat,â and hence the necessary political separation of the workersâ âsocial democracyâ from the mere âdemocracyâ of the bourgeois revolution, including the necessary separation from the âpetit bourgeois democratsâ who earned Marxâs most scathing scorn.
While liberals denied the need for such âsocial democracyâ and found political democracy to be sufficient, anarchists separated the social from the political, treating the latter as a fetishized realm of collusion in the bourgeois state and hence capitalism. Anarchists from the first, Proudhon, had avoided the issue of political revolution and the need to take state power; whereas Marxists had recognized that the crisis of capitalism inevitably resulted in political crisis and struggle over the state: If the working class failed to do so, others would step in their place. For Marx, the need for workersâ political revolution to achieve socialism was expressed by the phenomenon of Louis Bonaparteâs election in 1848 and coup dâĂ©tat in 1851, which expressed the inability of the âbourgeoisie to ruleâ any longer through civil society, while the proletariat was as yet politically undeveloped and thus ânot ready to ruleâ the state. But for Marx the necessity of the âdictatorship of the proletariatâ was that the âworkers must ruleâ politically in order to overcome capitalism economically and socially.
Marx characterized Louis Bonaparteâs politics as both âpetit bourgeoisâ and âlumpenproletarian,â finding support among the broad masses of capitalismâs discontented. But according to Marx their discontents could only reproduce capitalism since they could only at best join the working class or remain dependent on the realization of the value of its labor as a commodity. Hence, there was no possible withdrawal from the crisis of bourgeois politics and the democratic state, as by libertarians and anarchists, but the need to develop political power to overcome capitalism. For the capitalist wage-labor system with its far-reaching effects throughout society to be abolished required the political action of the wage laborers. That the âworkers must ruleâ meant that they needed to provide political leadership to the exploited and oppressed masses. If the organized working class did not, others would provide that leadership, as Bonaparte had done in 1848 and 1851. The means for this was the political party for socialism. As Luxemburg put it in her 1898 Stuttgart speech:
[B]y final goal we must not mean . . . this or that image of the future state, but the prerequisite for any future society, namely the conquest of political power. This conception of our task is closely related to our conception of capitalist society; it is the solid ground which underlies our view that capitalist society is caught in insoluble contradictions which will ultimately necessitate an explosion, a collapse, at which point we will play the role of the banker-lawyer who liquidates a bankrupt company.
The socialist political party was for Luxemburg the means for this necessary achievement of political power. But the party was not itself the solution, but rather the necessary manifestation and concretization of the problem of political power in capitalism and indeed the problem of âsocietyâ itself.
1905: party and class
Luxemburg took the occasion of the 1905 Revolution in Russia to critique the relation of labor unions and the Social-Democratic Party of Germany (SPD) in her pamphlet on The Mass Strike, the Political Party and the Trade Unions (1906). This was a continuation of Luxemburgâs criticism of the reformist Revisionist view of the relation of the economic and political struggles of the working class for socialism, which had found its strongest support among the labor union leadership. In bringing to bear the Russian experience in Germany, Luxemburg reversed the usual assumed hierarchy of German experience over Russian âbackwardness.â She also reversed the developmental order of economic and political struggles, the mistaken assumption that the economic must precede the political. The âmassâ or political strike had been associated with social- and political-historical primitiveness, with pre-industrial struggles and pre-Marxian socialism, specifically anarchism and anarcho-syndicalism (especially in the Latin countries), which had prioritized economic and social action over political action. Luxemburg sought to grasp the changed historical significance of the political strike; that it had become, rather, a symptom of advanced, industrial capitalism. In the 1905 Russian Revolution, the workers had taken political action before economic action, and the labor unions had originated out of that political action, rather than the reverse.
The western Russian Empire was rapidly industrialized and showed great social unrest in the 1890sâ1900s. It exhibited the most up-to-date techniques and organization in industrial production: The newest and largest factories in the world at this time were located in Russia. Luxemburg was active in the Russian Social-Democratic Labor Party (RSDLP) in the Russian part of Poland, through her own organization, the Social-Democratic Party of the Kingdom of Poland and Lithuania (SDKPiL). The 1905 Russian Revolution was precipitated by a political and not âeconomicâ crisis: the shaking of the Tsarist state in its losing war with Japan 1904â05. This was not merely a liberal-democratic discontent with the arbitrary rule of the Russian absolutism. For Luxemburg, the Russo-Japanese War was a symptom of capitalism, and so was the resulting crisis of Tsarism in Russia triggered by this war. The political strike was, as she put it, a revolt of âbourgeois Russia,â that is, of the modern industrial capitalists and workers, against Tsarism. What had started out in the united action of the capitalists and workers striking economically against the Tsarist state for liberal-democratic political reasons, unfolded into a class struggle by the workers against the capitalists. This was due to the necessity of reorganizing social provisions during the strike, in which mass-action strike committees took over the functions of the usual operations of capitalism and indeed of the Tsarist state itself. This had necessitated the formation of workersâ own collective-action organizations. Luxemburg showed how the economic organization of the workers had developed out of the political action against Tsarism, and that the basis of this was in the necessities of advanced industrial production. In this way, the workersâ actions had developed, beyond the liberal-democratic or âbourgeoisâ discontents and demands, into the tasks of âproletarian socialism.â Political necessity had led to economic necessity (rather than the reverse, economic necessity leading to political necessity).
For Luxemburg, this meant that the usual assumption in Germany that the political party, the SPD, was âbasedâ on the labor unions, was a profound mistake. The economic and social-cooperative actions of the unions were âbased,â for Luxemburg, on the political task of socialism and its political party. This meant prioritizing the political action of the socialist party as the real basis or substance of the economic and other social action of the working class. It was the political goal of the dictatorship of the proletariat through socialist revolution that gave actual substance to the workersâ economic struggles, which were, for Luxemburg, merely the necessary preparatory âschool of revolution.â
Luxemburg wrote her pamphlet while summering at a retreat with Lenin and other Bolsheviks in Finland. It was informed by her daily conversations with Lenin over many weeks. Lenin had previously written, in What is to be Done? (1902) (a pamphlet commissioned and agreed-upon by the Marxist faction of the RSDLP as a whole, those who later divided into Bolsheviks and Mensheviks), that economism and workerism in Russia had found support in Bernsteinian Revisionism in the SPD and the greater Second International, trying to subordinate the political struggle to economic struggle and thus to separate them. In so doing, they like the Revisionists had identified capitalist development with socialism rather than properly recognizing them as in growing contradiction. Lenin had, like Luxemburg, regarded such workerism and economism as âreformistâ in the sense of separating the workersâ struggles for reform from the goal of socialism that needed to inform such struggles. Luxemburg as well as Lenin called this âliquidationism,â or the dissolving of the goal into the movement, liquidating the need for the political party for socialism. In What is to be Done? Lenin had argued for the formation of a political party for the workersâ struggle for socialism in Russia. He took as polemical opponents those who, like the Revisionists in Germany, had deprioritized the necessity of the political party, thus deprioritizing the politics of the struggle for socialism, limiting it to economic action. (( See also my essay âLeninâs Liberalismâ, Platypus Review 36 (June 2011). Available online at: <http://platypus1917.org/2011/06/01/lenins-liberalism/>. )) The political party had thus redeemed itself in the 1905 Revolution in Russia, showing its necessary role for the workersâ political, social, and economic action, confirming Lenin and Luxemburgâs prior arguments against economism.
Luxemburg regarded the lessons of the 1905 Revolution in Russia to be a challenge to and hence a âcrisisââa potential critical turning pointâof the SPD in Germany. Continuing her prosecution of the Revisionist Dispute, Luxemburg argued for the concrete necessity of the political leadership of the party over the unions that had been demonstrated by the 1905 Revolution in Russia. By contrast, the tension and indeed contradiction between the goal of socialism and the preservation of the institutions of the workersâ movementâspecifically of the labor unionsâ self-interestâwhich might be threatened by the conservative reaction of the state against the political action of the socialist party, showed a conflict between movement and goal. The Revisionists thought that a mass political strike would merely provoke the Right into a coup dâĂ©tat.
Demand for redemption
Walter Benjamin, in his draft theses âOn the Concept of Historyâ (AKA âTheses on the Philosophy of History,â 1940), cited Luxemburg in particular when describing history itself as the âdemand for redemption.â Not only did Luxemburg raise this demand with her famous invocation of Marx and Engels on the crossroads in capitalism of âsocialism or barbarism,â but as a historical figure she herself calls out for such redemption.
The conflict in and about the party on which Luxemburg had focused was horribly revealed later by the outbreak of war in 1914, when a terrible choice seemed posed, between the political necessity to overthrow the Kaiserreich state to prevent or stop the war, and the need to preserve the workersâ economic and social organizations in the unions and the party. The war had been the Kaiserreichâs preemptive coup dâĂ©tat against the SPD. The party capitulated to this in that it facilitated and justified the unionsâ assertion of their self-preservation at the cost of cooperation with the stateâs war. This self-preservationâwhat Luxemburg excoriated as trying to âhide like a rabbit under a bushâ temporarily during the warâmay have been justified if these same organizations had served later to facilitate the political struggle for socialism after the Prussian Empire had been shaken by its loss in the war. But the SPDâs constraining of the workersâ struggles to preserve the state, limiting the German Revolution 1918â19 to a âdemocraticâ one against the threat of âBolshevism,â meant the partyâs suppression of its own membership. Past developments had prepared this. The Revisionistsâ prioritization of the movement and its organizations over the goal of socialism had been confirmed for what Luxemburg and Lenin had always warned against: the adaptation and liquidation of the working classâs struggles into, not a potential springboard for socialism, but rather a bulwark of capitalism; the transformation of the party from a revolutionary into a counterrevolutionary force. As Luxemburg had so eloquently put it in WWI, the SPD had become a âstinking corpseââsomething which had through the stench of decomposition revealed itself to have been dead for a long time alreadyâdead for the purposes of socialism. The party had killed itself through the Devilâs bargain of sacrificing its true political purpose for mere self-preservation.
In so doing, supposedly acting in the interests of the workers, the workersâ true interestsâin socialismâwere betrayed. As Luxemburg put it in the Junius Pamphlet, the failure of the SPD at the critical moment of 1914 had placed the entire history of the preceding â40 yearsâ of the struggles by the workersâsince the founding of the SPD in 1875ââin doubt.â Would this history be liquidated without redemption? This underscored Luxemburgâs warning, decades earlier, against dissolving the goal into the movement that would betray not only the goal but the movement itself. Reformist revisionism devoured itself. The only point of the party was its goal of revolution; without it, it was ânothingââindeed worse than nothing: It became a festering obstacle. The party was for Luxemburg not only or primarily the âsubjectâ but was also and especially the object of revolutionary struggle by the working class to achieve socialism. This is why the revolution that the party had facilitated was for Luxemburg merely the beginning and not the end of the struggle to achieve socialism. The political problem of capitalism was manifest in how the party pointed beyond itself in the revolution. But without the party, that problem could never even manifest let alone point beyond itself.
During the German Revolutionâprovoked by the collapse of the Kaiserreich at the end of WWIâLuxemburg split and founded the new Communist Party of Germany (KPD), joining Lenin in forming the âThirdâ or Communist International, in 1919: to make clear the political tasks that had been manifested and advanced but ultimately abdicated and failed by the social-democratic parties of the Second International in war and revolution. Just as Luxemburg and Lenin had always maintained that the political party for socialism was necessary to advance the contradiction and crisis of capitalism as it had developed from Marxâs time to their own, so it became necessary in crisis to split that party and found a new one. Turning the international war of capitalism into a socialist revolution meant manifesting a civil war within the workersâ movement and indeed within Marxism itself. Whereas her former comrades in the SPD recoiled from her apparent revolutionary fanaticism, and âsavedâ themselves and their party by betraying its goal (but ultimately faded from historical significance), Luxemburg, as a loyal party-member, sacrificed herself for the goal of socialism, redeeming her Marxism and making it profoundly necessary, thus tasking our remembrance and recovery of it today. |P